Liberals Sometimes Forget Inequality Matters When It Comes To Climate Change

If we’re serious about cost-benefit analysis, we have a duty to discount the interests of future generations

In the debate over climate change, people talk a lot about the cost of not doing anything. Yet its rarer to hear them talk about the cost of taking action to mitigate climate change’s effects. In order to determine what to do, we have to engage in a cost-benefit analysis, which by definition considers both aspects of the question.

Cost-benefit analysis is a method that economists often use to determine whether a policy should be adopted. It consists in estimating a trajectory over time for both the costs and the benefits that can be expected of the policy in question. For instance, if the policy consists in creating a carbon tax, the costs would be a rise of the price of energy, while the benefits would be a reduction of the damages resulting from the emission of greenhouse gases into the atmosphere. If the benefits outweigh the costs over the period of time under consideration, then adopting that policy could make sense, but otherwise it does not.


In the case of policies to mitigate climate change, the period of time under consideration in a cost-benefit analysis is very long because, according to the models scientists have developed, the worst consequences of climate change won’t really take place until a century from now or so.


I think there are very serious concerns about whether it’s realistic to think that we can estimate with any accuracy how the costs and benefits of any policy would evolve over such a long period of time. (To be clear, when I say that, it’s a huge understatement. What I really think is that, if people knew how the economic models used to make such monumental policy decisions work, there would be riots in the streets.) However, for the purposes of this post, I will just assume that it’s possible.


Now, even if we can estimate a trajectory over such a long period of time for the costs and benefits of a policy such as the adoption of a carbon tax, there remains the question of how we should discount both costs and benefits in the future. In the case of the debate about climate change, since economists think that most costs of a policy to mitigate it would be incurred during the initial period, while most benefits would accrue far in the future, the question is how benefits that would be enjoyed only by future generations should be discounted or even whether they should be discounted at all.


If the discount rate you are using in a cost-benefit analysis is r, it means that the value of a cost or benefit that accrues in the future is reduced by r every year. For instance, if the discount rate is 1% and the policy under consideration is expected to produce a benefit of $1 billion a century from now, then when compared to a cost incurred today this benefit would only be worth approximately $369 million.


Some think we shouldn’t discount benefits that would accrue to future generations at all because it’s immoral. The idea behind this claim is that future generations are not worth any less than us and, therefore, there is no reason to give more weight to a cost we’d have to incur than to a benefit that would accrue to them if we adopted a policy to mitigate the effects of climate change. In other words, on that view, any discount rate other than zero would be incompatible with intergenerational justice.


Virtually every economist would reject that claim. Even Nicholas Stern, whose report on climate change was criticized for using a discount rate that was deemed too low, used a non-zero discount rate. Yet since in my experience most people find it compelling, it’s useful to explain why that can’t be right.


The problem with that claim has to do with the fact that, as a result of economic growth, people in a century from now will be a lot richer than us.You may be tempted to say that we can’t assume economic growth will continue, but you have to realize that, if it did not, climate change would not even be a problem. Indeed, the models that are used to predict what is going to happen if we keep emitting greenhouse gases into the atmosphere assume that economic growth will continue — that’s precisely why they predict greenhouse gases emissions will continue to increase unless we do something. If economic growth stopped, emissions would not continue to increase and, as a result, there would no problem to mitigate in the first place. In his book on climate change, William Nordhaus assumes that GDP per capita will on average grow at a rate of approximately 2%, which after a century corresponds to a factor of approximately 7.2. In other words, according to the models used to predict the evolution of climate, people a century from now will on average be 7.2 times richer than us.


Now, this is relevant because pretty much everyone, including people who claim we shouldn’t discount benefits that accrue to future generations, agrees we should give more weight to costs incurred by relatively poor people than to benefits enjoyed by relatively well-off people. The reason is that we generally assume that, although well-being increases with income, the rate at which it does also decreases with income.


What this means is that a cost/benefit that is equivalent to the same amount of money is worth more for someone who is relatively poor than for someone who is relatively well-off. For instance, a loss of income of $5,000 is worth a lot more for someone who makes $20,000/year than for someone who makes $145,000/year, i. e. approximately 7.2 times more. (Remember that, according to the models used to predict the effects of greenhouse gases emissions, that’s how much richer than us on average people will be in a century.) For the guy who only makes $20,000/year, this could make the difference between sending his kids to a decent school and sending them to a shithole, whereas for the guy who makes $145,000/year it may just mean that he’ll have to wait a little longer before he buys another Mercedes.


Suppose we are considering a policy that would increase the income of people who make $145,000/year by $5,000/year, but decrease the income of people who make $20,000/year by $3,000/year. For someone who makes $20,000/year, $3,000/year is 15% of his income, which is pretty low to begin with. On the other hand, for someone who makes $145,000/year, $5,000/year is only 3.4% of his income. Assuming the number of people who make $145,000/year is the same as the number of people who make $20,000/year, if we used a discount rate of zero in the cost-benefit analysis for that policy, we’d conclude that we should adopt it because the benefits outweigh the costs.


The reaction to this proposal would be universal condemnation; it would be construed as utterly crazy and intolerably unfair. Yet, as far as the discount rate that we should use is concerned, there doesn’t seem to be any relevant difference between this case and the inter-generational case. Thus, if you think we should discount the benefits that would accrue to people who make $145,000/year in this case, then presumably you should also want to discount the benefits that would accrue to future generations from policies that mitigate climate change.


Obviously, there are a lot of complications involved in a cost-benefit analysis of climate change policy that I didn’t even get into. For instance, I completely ignored the issue of distributive justice, which is certainly important. Even in a century from now, some people still won’t be as rich as Westerners are today, so just looking at the average can be misleading. There’s a lot more to the question of discounting that I didn’t explore here, but what I’ve said is not controversial among people familiar with cost-benefit analysis.


The point has been to convince you that the discount rate should definitely not be zero, despite the intuition that many people have when they first hear about discounting.


Not only is it not immoral to discount the benefits that would accrue to future generations, but insofar as they will be relatively better-off compared to us, it would be immoral not to discount them.It’s interesting that, in my experience, people who are inclined to say we should use a discount rate of zero for the cost-benefit analysis of policies designed to mitigate the effects of climate change are typically liberals/progressives. Yet given that liberals/progressives are ordinarily more averse to inequality than other people, that’s exactly the opposite of what you’d expect if they were consistent. They seem to be making a difference between the ordinary case and the intergenerational case, but I can’t think of any reason to be more tolerant of inequality in the latter than in the former.


If you think that we should care less about people who are relatively better off, as I think you should, then it shouldn’t matter if they’re already alive or if they’re not born yet. 


Source: https://arcdigital.media/when-it-comes-to-climate-change-liberals-sometimes-forget-inequality-matters-a22150be87c4
By Philippe Lemoine

H2
H3
H4
3 columns
2 columns
1 column
3 Comments